Raising (linguistics)
In linguistics, raising constructions involve the movement of an argument from an embedded or subordinate clause to a matrix or main clause; in other words, a raising predicate/verb appears with a syntactic argument that is not its semantic argument, but is rather the semantic argument of an embedded predicate. Although English has raising constructions, not all languages do.
The term raising has its origins in the transformational analysis of such constructions; the constituent in question is seen as being "raised" from its initial, deep structure position as the subject of the embedded predicate to its surface structure position in the matrix predicate/verb.[1] Raising predicates/verbs are related to control predicates, although there are important differences between the two predicate/verb types.
Examples
There are at least two types of raising predicates/verbs: raising-to-subject verbs and raising-to-object predicates. Raising-to-object predicates overlap to a large extent with so-called ECM-verbs (= exceptional case-marking). These types of raising predicates/verbs are illustrated with the following sentences:
- a. They seem to be trying. - seem is a raising-to-subject verb.
- b. Prices appear to be increasing. - appear is a raising-to-subject verb.
- c. You seem to be impatient. - seem is a raising to subject verb.
- a. Fred wants us to help. - want can be a raising-to-object predicate.
- b. That proves him to be hiding something. - prove can be a raising-to-object predicate.
- c. She predicts there to be a problem. - predict can be a raising-to-object predicate.
The primary trait of raising predicates/verbs like these is that they are not semantically selecting one of their dependents.[2] The raising-to-subject verbs are not selecting their subject dependent, and the raising-to-object predicates are not selecting their object dependent. These dependents appear to have been raised from the lower predicate.
Alternation with it-extraposition
Raising predicates/verbs can be identified in part by the fact that they alternatively take a full clause dependent and can take part in it-extraposition,[3] e.g.
- a. Tom seems to have won the race.
- b. It seems that Tom won the race. - Raising-to-subject verb seem occurs with it-extraposition
- a. Larry appears to be doing the work.
- b. It appears that Larry is doing the work. - Raising-to-subject predicate verb appear occurs with it-extraposition.
- a. Sam believed someone to know the answer.
- b. Sam believed it that someone knew the answer. - Raising-to-object predicate believe occurs with it-extraposition.
- c. Sam believed that someone knew the answer. - Raising-to-object predicate believe occurs with clausal object argument.
- a. That proves Susan to be a jackass.
- b. That proves it that Susan is a jackass. - Raising-to-object predicate prove occurs with it-extraposition.
- c. That proves that Susan is a jackass. - Raising-to-object predicate prove occurs with clausal object argument.
Raising predicates/verbs can appear with it-extraposition and/or a full clausal dependent. They appear to be subcategorizing for a propositional argument.
Raising-to-subject verbs vs. auxiliary verbs
The raising-to-subject verbs seem and appear are similar to auxiliary verbs insofar as both verb types have little to no semantic content. The content that they do have is functional in nature. In this area, auxiliary verbs cannot be viewed as separate predicates; they are, rather, part of a predicate. The raising-to-subject verbs seem and appear are similar insofar it is difficult to view them as predicates. They serve, rather, to modify a predicate. That this is so can be seen in the fact that the following pairs of sentences are essentially synonymous:
- a. Fred does not seem to have done it.
- b. Fred seems not to have done it. - Position of the negation is flexible.
- a. Mary does not appear to like pudding.
- b. Mary appears not to like pudding. - Position of the negation is flexible.
The fact that position of the negation can change without influencing the meaning is telling. It means that the raising-to-subject verbs can hardly be viewed as predicates.
While raising-to-subject verbs are like auxiliary verbs insofar as they lack the content of predicates, they are unlike auxiliaries in syntactic respects. Auxiliary verbs undergo subject-aux inversion, raising-to-subject verbs do not. Auxiliary verbs license negation, raising-to-subject verbs do so only reluctantly:
- a. Fred is happy.
- b. Is Fred happy? - Auxiliary verb be takes part in subject-auxiliary inversion.
- c. Fred is not happy. - Auxiliary verb be licenses negation.
- a. Fred seems happy.
- b. *Seems Fred happy? - Raising-to-subject verb seem cannot take part in subject-auxiliary inversion.
- c. ??Fred seems not happy. - Raising-to-subject verb seem can hardly license negation.
- a. Susan should stay.
- b. Should Susan stay? - Modal auxiliary should takes part in subject-auxiliary inversion.
- c. Susan should not stay. - Modal auxiliary should can license negation.
- a. Susan appears to be staying.
- b. *Appears Susan to be staying? - Raising-to-subject verb appear cannot take part in subject-auxiliary inversion.
- c. ?Susan appears not to be staying. - Raising-to-subject verb appear reluctantly licenses negation.
Raising-to-object verbs are also clearly NOT auxiliary verbs. Unlike raising-to-subject verbs, however, raising-to-object verbs have clear semantic content, so they are hence indisputably predicates.
Representing raising
The fact that the raised constituent behaves as though it is a dependent of the higher predicate is generally reflected in the syntax trees that are employed to represent raising structures. The following trees are illustrative of the type of structures assumed for raising-to-object predicates.[4][5] Both constituency-based trees of phrase structure grammar and dependency-based trees of dependency grammar are employed here:[6]
The constituency-based trees are the a-trees on the left, and the dependency-based trees are the b-trees on the right. While the structures assumed here can be disputed - especially the constituency structures - the trees all show the main stance toward raising structures. This stance is that the "subject" of the lower predicate appears as a dependent of the higher predicate - the relevant constituents are in bold. Relatively flat structures are assumed to accommodate this behavior. Both it and the claim are shown as dependents of expects and proves, respectively, although they are semantic arguments of the lower predicates to happen and to be false, respectively.
A number of empirical considerations support the relatively flat structures shown here. That is, empirical considerations support the position of the "raised" constituent as a dependent of the matrix predicate/verb. These dependents can appear in object form, they can appear as the subject of passive sentences, and they can appear as reflexives coindexed with the matrix subjects:[7]
- a. We expect him to help. - Pronoun him appears in object form.
- b. He is expected to help. - Object pronoun becomes subject in passive.
- c. He1 expects himself1 to help. - Reflexive is coindexed with subject.
- a. You proved her to be competent. - Pronoun her appears in object form.
- b. She was proved to be competent. - Object pronoun becomes subject in passive.
- c. She1 proved herself1 to be competent. - Reflexive is coindexed with subject.
This behavior speaks strongly for the general analysis reflected in the trees, namely that the "raised" constituent is a dependent of the higher predicate.
Raising vs. control
An understanding of raising is significantly expanded by comparing and contrasting raising with control. Examine the following (dependency) trees:
The a-trees contain the raising predicates wants and judges, whereas the b-trees contain the control predicates told and asked. Despite the fact that structures assumed for these different predicate types are essentially the same, there is a major distinction to be drawn. This distinction is that the control predicates semantically select their objects, whereas the raising predicates do not. In other words, the object is a semantic argument of the control predicate in each case, whereas it is not an argument of the raising predicate. This situation obtains despite the fact that both predicate types take the object to be the "subject" of the lower predicate.
The distinction between raising-to-object and control predicates is identified using the there-insertion diagnostic. Expletive there can appear as the object (or subject) of raising predicates, but it cannot appear as the object of control predicates,[8] e.g.:
- a. Sam judges there to be a problem. - Expletive there can appear as the object of a raising-to-object predicate.
- b. *Sam asked there to be a problem. - Expletive there cannot appear as the object of an object control predicate.
- a. We want there to be a revision. - Expletive there can appear as the object of a raising-to-object predicate.
- b. ??We helped there (to) be a revision. - Expletive there cannot appear as the object of an object control predicate.
Since the raising predicates place no semantic restrictions on their object dependents, expletive there is free to appear. In contrast, object control predicates do place semantic restrictions on their object arguments, which means expletive there usually cannot appear.
Notes
- ↑ Early seminal accounts of raising were produced by Rosenbaum (1967) and Postal (1974). See further Grinder and Elgin (1973:141ff.), Bach (1974:120ff., 146ff.), Emonds (1976:75ff.), Borsley (1996:126-144), Carnie (2007:285ff.).
- ↑ That raising predicates, unlike control predicates, do not semantically select one of their arguments is emphasized in all accounts of raising and control. See for instance van Riemsdijk and Williams (1986:130), Borsley (1996:133), Culicover (1997:102).
- ↑ Concerning the ability of raising predicates to appear with full clausal arguments, see Bach (1974:149), Borsley (1996:127f.), Carnie (2007:291).
- ↑ The flat VP analysis of raising structures shown in the a-sentences was posited by some in the 1970s and later. For examples of the "flat" analysis, see for instance Bach (1974:146), Emonds (1976:77), and Borsley (1996:128). Most modern dependency grammars (also) assume a flat structure for raising structures.
- ↑ For an early layered analysis, however, see Culicover (1982:251ff.).
- ↑ The dependency trees are like those found, for instance, in Osborne et al. (2012).
- ↑ Concerning these points, see Bach (1974:147f.), Postal (1974), Lasnik and Saito (1999:9ff.).
- ↑ The expletive is widely employed to distinguish control from raising constructions. Concerning there-insertion as a diagnostic for distinguishing between control and raising, see for instance Grinder and Elgin (1973:142-143), Bach (1973:151), Culicover (1982:256ff.), Borsley (1996:127), Culicover (1997:102), Lasnik and Saito (1999:8-9), Falk (2001:131).
References
- Bach, E. 1974. Syntactic theory. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, Inc.
- Borsley, R. 1996. Modern phrase structure grammar. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell Publishers.
- Carnie, A. 2007. Syntax: A generative introduction, 2nd edition. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.
- Cowper, E. 1992. A concise introduction to syntactic theory: The government-binding approach. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.
- Culicover, P. 1982. Syntax, 2nd edition. New York: Academic Press.
- Culicover, P. 1997. Principles and Parameters: An introduction to syntactic theory. Oxford University Press.
- Emonds, J. 1976. A transformational approach to English syntax: Root, structure-preserving, and local transformations, New York: Academic Press.
- Falk, Y. 2001. Lexical-Functional Grammar: An introduction to parallel constraint-based syntax. Stanford, CA: CSLI Publications.
- Grinder, J. and S. Elgin. 1973. Guide to transformational grammar: History, theory, and practice. New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston, Inc.
- Haegeman, L. 1994. Introduction to government and binding theory, 2nd edition. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
- Lasnik, H. and M. Saito. 1999. On the subject of infinitives. In H. Lasnik, Minimalist analysis, 7-24. Malden, MA: Blackwell.
- Osborne, T., Michael P., and T. Groß 2012. Catenae: Introducing a novel unit of syntactic analysis. Syntax 15, 4, 354-396.
- Postal, P. 1974. On raising: One rule of English grammar and its theoretical implications. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
- van Riemsdijk, H. and E. Williams. 1986. Introduction to the theory of grammar. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
- Rosenbaum, P. 1967. The grammar of English predicate complement constructions. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.